Senin, 08 Agustus 2011

The History of Philosophy as Philosophy: (5). Reading Forward, Reading Backward

















Historians of philosophy
differ in their strategies for seeking a
context.
Some interpreters, such as Gaukroger or Buchdahl, read
forward:
they take the period preceding and surrounding a given
author
as the primary context. Others employ a strategy of reading
backward. Friedman, in Kant and
the Exact Sciences
, uses some


preceding material (especially in considering Kant’s
Newtonianism).
But in addressing Kant’s philosophy of mathematics,
he
reads backward from the perspective of
late-nineteenth-century
developments in mathematics
and logic. He adopts attitudes that
were not
available before the late nineteenth century about the
relation
between logic and mathematics and about the subjectmatter
of
mathematics itself, and he then interprets Kant by
considering
how his work anticipated or fell short of the standards
set by
these ways of thinking.





A primary aspect of
Friedman’s reconstruction concerns
Kant’s
proposal that geometrical proofs require appeal to spatial
intuition.
Kant makes the point most clearly in the Doctrine of
Method
in the first
Critique, where
he argues that, in geometry,
synthetic
procedures relying on spatial intuition are needed; discursive
logic and the analysis of concepts are
insufficient by themselves.
Friedman
sees this appeal to spatial intuition as arising
because
the logical resources available to Kant (monadic logic)
were
inadequate for logically constructing continuous magnitude
(either
the real number line, or a weaker subset of the reals, the
rationals
together with square roots). For example, if Kant had
been
asked to defend the proposition that a line-segment crossing
the circumference of a circle (it starts
inside and ends outside the
circle)
intersects that circumference, he could only have appealed
to
constructive procedures that relied on spatial structure. After
geometry had been interpreted on an
algebraic foundation in
the nineteenth century, so
that line-segments and arcs of circles were
constituted
as loci of point co-ordinates, a proof of this intersection
could be provided algebraically. If one wished in this context to interpret the real number line
logically, one could construct a pointspace
with
irrational co-ordinates (and thus betweenness relations
appropriately
dense for the problem) by employing the dependence
relations
for universal and existential quantifiers of modern polyadic
logic. But Friedman has Kant realizing
that his own (monadic)
logical resources could not
establish such a point-space, and turning
to
iterative constructive procedures (in a spatial medium) to get it
done. Accordingly, Kant would
demonstrate the appropriate infinity
of
points, including the point of intersection, through infinitely (or
indefinitely) iterated procedures of
construction (constructing one
point,
then another, with compass-and-straight-edge procedures
that
include square-root line-lengths).





This retrospective reading
ignores the facts that, in Kant’s time,
geometry
was commonly considered to be more basic than algebra,
and
geometrical structures were not thought to be composed of or
constructed from points or point-sets.
The idea of deriving all
geometrical
structures from algebraic relations was foreign to
mathematics,
certainly at the basic level at which Kant taught and
understood
mathematics. (Euler and others were laying the foundation
for
algebraization, but Kant didn’t contend with that level of
mathematics.)





In the Critique, Kant offered a good
philosophical reconstruction
of the
actual procedures of proof used in Euclid’s geometry and its
common eighteenth-century expressions.
Lisa Shabel has shown
that these procedures did not
rely primarily on logical structure, but
often
drew upon the spatial relations exhibited in diagrams constructible
with only compass and straight-edge.
These constructive
procedures were not used to
demonstrate the existence of an infinite
structure;
infinite spatial structure (or continuous, in the sense of
unbroken)
was assumed. For example, if a proof required placing a
point on
a line-segment between its two end-points, the procedure
relied
on the assumed spatial structure of the line-segment. That is,
it was taken as given that all points of
the segment lie
between the two end-points; a point located anywhere
on the segment was
already known to be between
the end-points, and its existence need
not be
proved. As Shabel argues, Kant’s discussions in the
Critique captured the ineliminable role of such
appeals to spatial structure in
the
proofs of the extant Euclidean geometry. In this context,
questions
about the existence of the point where a line crosses a
circle
do not arise; such problems first arise with the nineteenthcentury
reconception of geometry in algebraic
terms.





A reconstruction of Kant’s
philosophy of mathematics should,
at the
outset, pay close attention to the actual mathematical
conceptions
and practices of Kant and his predecessors. By
allowing
a later understanding of the problems and methods of
geometry
to set the context, Friedman missed fundamental aspects
of
Kant’s theory and achievement. Whereas Kant appealed to
spatial
intuition because he recognized the role of spatial structure
in Euclid’s proofs, Friedman instead
sees him as responding to
questions
that arose only fifty or one hundred years later by
employing
a counterpart to modern logical techniques. In writing
the
history and philosophy of mathematics, it will be more fruitful
to read forward, by asking how the
problems and methods of
geometry were conceived at
one time and then came to be
reconceived
later. Kant’s position will not be most fruitfully
characterized
as ‘not yet using’ the later methods, or as ‘using this
work-around’
to solve the later problems. Taking earlier mathematics
and
philosophy on their own terms will help locate the
specific
problems and opportunities that motivated or afforded
later
developments.





I do not suggest that reading
backward is never useful. I do
suggest
that reading forward is more often useful in setting context.
Reading backward should come later, in
posing questions about
shapes and themes in history.








Source : Sorell, Tom and
G. A. J. Rogers.(2005), Analytic Philosophy
and
History of Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon
Press
).











Tidak ada komentar:

Posting Komentar