Rabu, 10 Agustus 2011

The History of Philosophy as Philosophy: (6). Expanding contexts, seeking Historical themes











The ‘context’ for reading
early modern philosophy can be as narrow
as the
text surrounding a passage (or the corpus containing a
work),
and (in the limit) as broad as human history itself. Initial
steps in expanding the context of early
modern philosophy came
from taking seriously the
aims of philosophers as expressed in their
works.
Such ‘internal’ contexts would have been sufficient (even if
other evidence were not available) for
expanding the context of
early
modern metaphysics and epistemology to include relations to
mathematics, physics, and other
scientific areas such as biology,
physiology,
or psychology. An internal context is also sufficient
for
expanding consideration of early modern theories of mind to
include theories of the senses, of
cognition more generally, and of
the
passions and emotions. Further extension from within is in
order.
Religion and theology are major presences in early modern
philosophical
texts. Rather than seeing them as encumbrances to be
overcome
(one common view), or as sources of arguments to be
retrieved
by today’s believers (another trend), one might make the
relations
among philosophy, religion, and theology an object of
investigation
in its own right.





There is more to history of
philosophy than taking the contexts of
individual
works or authors into account in reconstructing or
explaining
their positions. Other units of investigation can be
defined,
including ideas and themes. One sort of thematic investigation
would follow key philosophical ideas or
subject areas over
decades or centuries. These
might include basic philosophical
notions,
such as conceptions of knowledge and its forms, technical
notions,
such as ‘a priori’ and ‘a posteriori’ or ‘analysis’ and
‘synthesis’,
or general categories, such as ‘metaphysics’ or even
‘philosophy’.
Such basic work in ‘philosophical history of ideas’ is
needed
to support contextual work in the history of philosophy. But
it can be of interest in its own right,
in uncovering conceptual
changes
and their philosophical significance. Louis Loeb’s examination
of causation and substance in early
modern philosophy is a
recent example of this sort
of thematic history.





Other work can attend to the
ways in which philosophers
have
been read or ‘received’. To understand seventeenth-century
Aristotelianism
and its opponents, an interpreter must distinguish
the
local Aristotelianism from the historical Aristotle. The same
goes for every major figure. Histories
of how the works of key
figures were received,
initially and over the centuries, are of great
interest.
Kant’s own presentation of his critical philosophy was
altered
as he responded to its initial reception. His works have been
constantly studied since their
appearance, with differing emphases.
The
historical work of untangling these threads can provide distance
from today’s locally received readings
of Kant, as well as
presenting various
possibilities, live or not, for interpreting or
adapting
his work.





Additional historical and
thematic connections should be sought
across
the boundaries of traditional periods. The relation between
early modern philosophy and
nineteenth-century philosophy might
be taken
beyond obvious connections such as that between Kant
and
German idealism, or between Locke and Hume and the two
Mills.
By the early twentieth century, the gross structure of periods
and themes used in presenting the
history of modern philosophy
(into
the nineteenth century) had solidified. Looking back now from
the early twenty-first century, we may
reconsider these received
views
and ask how the story continues. The impact of Darwinism
on
philosophy might be studied more fully. Links between the
flourishing
American philosophy before
1930 and the philosophy and science of the preceding century
might be investigated. The
development
of history of philosophy in America throughout the
twentieth
century deserves further exploration.





In moving beyond contextual
readings of individual texts or
authors,
the history of philosophy will develop historical accounts
and
explanations of larger movements of ideas. As history of
philosophy, these
accounts will focus on internal intellectual factors.
As history of philosophy, they will, as
needed, relate these factors to
wider
historical factors and trends.








Source : Sorell, Tom and
G. A. J. Rogers.(2005), Analytic Philosophy
and
History of Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon
Press
).








Tidak ada komentar:

Posting Komentar